Heideggers Conceptual Essences: Being and the Nothing, Humanism, and Technology Being and the Nothing are the same. The ancient philosopher Lao-tzu believed that the world entertains no separations and that opposites do not actually exist. His grounding for this seemingly preposterous proposition lies in the fact that because alleged opposites depend on one another and their definitions rely on their differences, they cannot possibly exist without each other. Therefore, they are not actually opposites. The simple and uncomplex natured reasoning behind this outrageous statement is useful when trying to understand and describe Martin Heideggers deeply leveled philosophy of Being and the nothing. Lao-tzus uncomplicated rationale used in stating that supposed opposites create each other, so cannot be opposite, is not unlike Heideggers description of the similarity between the opposites Being and the nothing. Unlike Lao-tzu, Heidegger does not claim that no opposites exist. He does however say that two obviously opposite concepts are the same, and in this way, the two philosophies are similar. He believes that the separation of beings from Being creates the nothing between them. Without the nothing, Being would cease to be. If there were not the nothing, there could not be anything, because this separation between beings and Being is necessary. Heidegger even goes so far as to say that Being itself actually becomes the nothing via its essential finity. This statement implies a synonymity between the relation of life to death and the relation of Being to nothingness. To Heidegger, the only end is death. It is completely absolute, so it is a gateway into the nothing. This proposition makes Being and the nothing the two halves of the whole. Both of their roles are equally important and necessary in the cycle of life and death. Each individual life inevitably ends in death, but without this death, Life would be allowed no progression: The nothing does not merely serve as the counterconcept of beings; rather, it originally belongs to their essential unfolding as such (104). Likewise, death cannot occur without finite life. In concordance with the statement that the nothing separates beings from Being, the idea that death leads to the nothing implies that death is just the loss of the theoretical sandwich's bread slices, leaving nothing for the rest of ever. The existence of death, therefore, is much more important in the whole because it magnifies the nothing into virtually everything. The magnification of the nothing serves as an equalizer between Being and nothing because Being is so robust and obvious that it magnifies itself. In this case, the opposites are completely reliant on each other, not only conceptually but physically. Heidegger gives new meaning to Lao-tzus philosophy that opposites define each other when he tries to uncover the true essence and meaning of Being, and he reveals another level of intertwination between the nothing and Being. In order to define Being, it is mandatory to step outside of it, into the nothing because: Everything we talk about, mean, and are related to in such and such a way is in Being. What and how we are ourselves are is also in Being. Being is found in thatness and whatness, reality, the being at hand of things [Vorhandenheit], subsistence, validity, existence [Dasein], and in the there is [es gibt] (47). Heidegger is very adamant on the importance of unbiased judgments and definitions, and how could he possibly calculate the exact meaning of Being while viewing it from a state of Being? Thus it is necessary to step out into the nothing to fully comprehend Being. For this reason, human beings are the only beings capable of pondering the essence of existence and nonexistence. Dasein are the only creatures capable because they are held out into the nothing: Being and the nothing do belong together . . . because Being itself is essentially finite and reveals itself only in the transcendence of Dasein which is held out into the nothing (108). The highest determinations of the essence of man in humanism still do not realize the proper dignity of man (233). When Heidegger rejects the title humanist, it is not because he is anti-humanity or even pessimistic about the fate of the human race. Rather, he rejects the category because he rightly sees humanism as defined with man at the center, which is a point of view he very strongly rejects. Perhaps in some other era, Heidegger could fittingly be called a humanist; however, he believes that the word humanism ... has lost its meaning (247). The modern connotation of humanism is not suitable for Heidegger mainly because in relation to the cosmos, other beings, and even life itself, Heidegger believes that man is essentially out of control. Instead of Heideggers philosophy revolving around mankind, it is centered on the question of Being. Dasein is often the main character of Heideggers elaboration, but not because he is the center. Instead, it is because he is the mechanism through which the nothing and hence the answer to Being can be discovered: If the answer to the question of Being thus becomes the guiding directive for research, then it is sufficiently given only if the specific mode of being of previous ontology--the vicissitudes of its questioning, its findings, and its failures--becomes visible as necessary to the very character of Dasein (62-63). Because of their trancendence and resulting link to Being and the nothing, they are the best route to the answer of Being. Even his focus on Dasein, however, leaves no trace of humanistic qualities: he doesnt even keep the title human: The analysis of Dasein thus understood is wholly oriented toward the guiding task of working out the question of Being (60). When Heidegger does speak of humanitys goodness, he does not incorporate the entire species in his statements. Only a percentage of the race is included in his vision of humanity. This is because he sees humanity as a goal for mankind. If he were reffering to all of humanity, wouldnt he just use the word mankind? Heidegger believes that part of mans essence is the ability to step out of his essence. This ability he calls ekstaticism, and it means that there is no question as to whether or not man is at the center. The answer is no because man is actually outside of what humanity claims revolves around men. This transcendence is often unrecognized to the point of causing man not to understand or fully evaluate his environment, which just reiterates that he is not in control: Because man as the one who ek-sists comes to stand in this relation that Being destines for itself, in that he ... takes it upon himself, he at first fails to recognize the nearest and attaches himself to the next nearest. He even thinks that this is nearest (235). Paradoxically, this eksistence characteristic of Dasein, which gives him the ability to transcend and reach a level of humanity also can cause inhumane acts. In this way, the possibilities of eksistence threaten its goals: the inhumanity that mankind is capable of threaten the very concept of humanity. If man were at the center, he would be granted control. His control would be indicated by his initiation, recognition, and decision. But he is not the beginning or the end, and neither does he understand them. From the point of view of Heidegger, control is something men obviously lack. Man is not even in control of his own existence. He does not decide to be given life. Being is given to man, but man does not command it; man occurs essentially in such a way that he is the there ... that is, the clearing of Being (229). Man through thinking takes over this gift, but does not own it. Man does not even own his thoughts. Being does not revolve around man. Man is thrown into his eksistence; Da-sein itself occurs essentially as thrown (231). Man revolves around Being, and serves as one of Beings expressions. Humanity believes that because man is the center, it is his place to rule over all other life forms on the planet. Heidegger strongly refutes this notion. He recognizes the elementary aspect to the logic applied in the claim that because men are more intelligent than animals, they are better. First of all, men are not mere animals. They exist differently because of their ability to step out of their essence and into the nothing. People and animals are different, so they are not comparable. The elementary concept that man is an animal better than other animals implies prejudice against less intellectual persons. Technologys essence, relationship with man, and future are at the hands of Being, not humanity. Heidegger's views of technology and its relation to ethics are complicated and difficult, not unlike his views on nearly everything else. He saw the journey of technology as an inevitable process that began slowly but quickened via its vicissitudes. He sees the process as a means to an end. However, this means to an end is different from most means to an end because its end is more means, so it inevitably progresses faster and faster. In other words, the result of technology is more and more technology in larger and larger amounts. Also, he believed that its progression is out of our control. Technology is inarguably the result of thinking. Heidegger claims that no thought is original in that the thinker does not actually conjure it. Rather, the thought reveals itself to the thinker, even if he is the first person to ever think of it. So, human beings are not the creators of technology even if they created it because the thinker only respond[s] to what address[es] itself to him (323). In this way, technology existed even before some prehistoric ape scraped some bugs out of a piece of bark with a twig. This means that there must be some other cause for technology besides man. Heidegger says, thinking, propriated by Being, belongs to Being. At the same time thinking is of Being insofar as thinking, belonging to Being, listens to Being. As the belonging to Being that listens, thinking is what it is according to its essential origin (220). The combonation of these two quotes means that Being actually created technology with thought as its messenger to humanity. The handing over of the invention of technology to Being intensely complicates things. Now finding technologys essence becomes almost as difficult as finding Beings definition. Of course, it was necessary for Heidegger to understand the essence of technology. The importance is due to the fact that man cannot gain control or understanding of technology without knowing its essence and attaining a free relationship with it (311). By free, he means free of bondage, subjectivity, and slavery. One cannot objectively calculate the implications of technology while bound to it by lifestyle, opinionated about it, or reliant on it to the point of slavery. This freedom is granted by looking at the big picture, way back before technology in the modern sense existed, even with the apes. This allows one to view technology with unbiased eyes. Then, the will to mastery becomes all the more urgent the more tecchnology threatens to slip from human control (313). The only control humanity has over technology is in internal will that leads to understanding of the essence and eventually to mastery. Technology's essence has two equal conceptual divisions which are reliant on each other: (1) technology as instrumental and as (2) a human activity. Its means that lead to more means also have two characters: (1) that of revealing and (2) that of self-creation. Thus, technology is an instrumental human activity that self-creates its revealing with vicissitude. It cannot be controlled unless the complexity of these concepts are understood. Words: 1963